In transcendental number theory, a mathematical discipline, Baker's theorem gives a lower bound for the absolute value of linear combinations of logarithms of algebraic numbers. The result, proved by Alan Baker (1966, 1967a, 1967b), subsumed many earlier results in transcendental number theory and solved a problem posed by Alexander Gelfond nearly fifteen years earlier.[1] Baker used this to prove the transcendence of many numbers, to derive effective bounds for the solutions of some Diophantine equations, and to solve the class number problem of finding all imaginary quadratic fields with class number 1.

History

To simplify notation, let be the set of logarithms to the base e of nonzero algebraic numbers, that is

where denotes the set of complex numbers and denotes the algebraic numbers (the algebraic closure of the rational numbers ). Using this notation, several results in transcendental number theory become much easier to state. For example the Hermite–Lindemann theorem becomes the statement that any nonzero element of is transcendental.

In 1934, Alexander Gelfond and Theodor Schneider independently proved the Gelfond–Schneider theorem. This result is usually stated as: if is algebraic and not equal to 0 or 1, and if is algebraic and irrational, then is transcendental. The exponential function is multi-valued for complex exponents, and this applies to all of its values, which in most cases constitute infinitely many numbers. Equivalently, though, it says that if are linearly independent over the rational numbers, then they are linearly independent over the algebraic numbers. So if and is not zero, then the quotient is either a rational number or transcendental. It cannot be an algebraic irrational number like .

Although proving this result of "rational linear independence implies algebraic linear independence" for two elements of was sufficient for his and Schneider's result, Gelfond felt that it was crucial to extend this result to arbitrarily many elements of Indeed, from Gel'fond (1960, p. 177):

one may assume that the most pressing problem in the theory of transcendental numbers is the investigation of the measures of transcendence of finite sets of logarithms of algebraic numbers.

This problem was solved fourteen years later by Alan Baker and has since had numerous applications not only to transcendence theory but in algebraic number theory and the study of Diophantine equations as well. Baker received the Fields medal in 1970 for both this work and his applications of it to Diophantine equations.

Statement

With the above notation, Baker's theorem is a nonhomogeneous generalization of the Gelfond–Schneider theorem. Specifically it states:

Baker's Theorem  If are linearly independent over the rational numbers, then for any algebraic numbers not all zero, we have

where H is the maximum of the heights of and C is an effectively computable number depending on n, and the maximum d of the degrees of (If β0 is nonzero then the assumption that are linearly independent can be dropped.) In particular this number is nonzero, so 1 and are linearly independent over the algebraic numbers.

Just as the Gelfond–Schneider theorem is equivalent to the statement about the transcendence of numbers of the form ab, so too Baker's theorem implies the transcendence of numbers of the form

where the bi are all algebraic, irrational, and 1, b1, …, bn are linearly independent over the rationals, and the ai are all algebraic and not 0 or 1.

Baker (1977) also gave several versions with explicit constants. For example, if has height at most and all the numbers have height at most then the linear form

is either 0 or satisfies

where

and the field generated by and over the rationals has degree at most d. In the special case when β0 = 0 and all the are rational integers, the rightmost term log Ω can be deleted.

An explicit result by Baker and Wüstholz for a linear form Λ with integer coefficients yields a lower bound of the form

where

and d is the degree of the number field generated by the

Baker's method

Baker's proof of his theorem is an extension of the argument given by Gel'fond (1960, chapter III, section 4). The main ideas of the proof are illustrated by the proof of the following qualitative version of the theorem of Baker (1966) described by Serre (1971):

If the numbers are linearly independent over the rational numbers, for nonzero algebraic numbers then they are linearly independent over the algebraic numbers.

The precise quantitative version of Baker's theory can be proved by replacing the conditions that things are zero by conditions that things are sufficiently small throughout the proof.

The main idea of Baker's proof is to construct an auxiliary function of several variables that vanishes to high order at many points of the form then repeatedly show that it vanishes to lower order at even more points of this form. Finally the fact that it vanishes (to order 1) at enough points of this form implies using Vandermonde determinants that there is a multiplicative relation between the numbers ai.

Construction of the auxiliary function

Assume there is a relation

for algebraic numbers α1, …, αn, β1, …, βn−1. The function Φ is of the form

The integer coefficients p are chosen so that they are not all zero and Φ and its derivatives of order at most some constant M vanish at for integers with for some constant h. This is possible because these conditions are homogeneous linear equations in the coefficients p, which have a non-zero solution provided the number of unknown variables p is larger than the number of equations. The linear relation between the logs of the α's is needed to cut down the number of linear equations that have to be satisfied. Moreover, using Siegel's lemma, the sizes of the coefficients p can be chosen to be not too large. The constants L, h, and M have to be carefully adjusted so that the next part of the proof works, and are subject to some constraints, which are roughly:

  • L must be somewhat smaller than M to make the argument about extra zeros below work.
  • A small power of h must be larger than L to make the final step of the proof work.
  • Ln must be larger than about Mn−1h in order that it is possible to solve for the coefficients p.

The constraints can be satisfied by taking h to be sufficiently large, M to be some fixed power of h, and L to be a slightly smaller power of h. Baker took M to be about h2 and L to be about h2−1/2n.

The linear relation between the logarithms of the α's is used to reduce L slightly; roughly speaking, without it the condition Ln must be larger than about Mn−1h would become Ln must be larger than about Mnh, which is incompatible with the condition that L is somewhat smaller than M.

Zeros of the auxiliary function

The next step is to show that Φ vanishes to slightly smaller order at many more points of the form for integers l. This idea was Baker's key innovation: previous work on this problem involved trying to increase the number of derivatives that vanish while keeping the number of points fixed, which does not seem to work in the multivariable case. This is done by combining two ideas; First one shows that the derivatives at these points are quite small, by using the fact that many derivatives of Φ vanish at many nearby points. Then one shows that derivatives of Φ at this point are given by algebraic integers times known constants. If an algebraic integer has all its conjugates bounded by a known constant, then it cannot be too small unless it is zero, because the product of all conjugates of a nonzero algebraic integer is at least 1 in absolute value. Combining these two ideas implies that Φ vanishes to slightly smaller order at many more points This part of the argument requires that Φ does not increase too rapidly; the growth of Φ depends on the size of L, so requires a bound on the size of L, which turns out to be roughly that L must be somewhat smaller than M. More precisely, Baker showed that since Φ vanishes to order M at h consecutive integers, it also vanishes to order M/2 at h1+1/8n consecutive integers 1, 2, 3, …. Repeating this argument J times shows that Φ vanishes to order M/2J at h1+J/8n points, provided that h is sufficiently large and L is somewhat smaller than M/2J.

One then takes J large enough that:

(J larger than about 16n will do if h2 > L) so that:

Completion of the proof

By definition can be written as:

Therefore as l varies we have a system of (L + 1)n homogeneous linear equations in the (L + 1)n unknowns which by assumption has a non-zero solution, which in turn implies the determinant of the matrix of coefficients must vanish. However this matrix is a Vandermonde matrix and the formula for the determinant of such a matrix forces an equality between two of the values:

so are multiplicatively dependent. Taking logs shows that are linearly dependent over the rationals.

Extensions and generalizations

Baker (1966) in fact gave a quantitative version of the theorem, giving effective lower bounds for the linear form in logarithms. This is done by a similar argument, except statements about something being zero are replaced by statements giving a small upper bound for it, and so on.

Baker (1967a) showed how to eliminate the assumption about 2πi in the theorem. This requires a modification of the final step of the proof. One shows that many derivatives of the function vanish at z = 0, by an argument similar to the one above. But these equations for the first (L+1)n derivatives again give a homogeneous set of linear equations for the coefficients p, so the determinant is zero, and is again a Vandermonde determinant, this time for the numbers λ1 log α1 + ⋯ + λn log αn. So two of these expressions must be the same which shows that log α1,…,log αn are linearly dependent over the rationals.

Baker (1967b) gave an inhomogeneous version of the theorem, showing that

is nonzero for nonzero algebraic numbers β0, …, βn, α1, …, αn, and moreover giving an effective lower bound for it. The proof is similar to the homogeneous case: one can assume that

and one inserts an extra variable z0 into Φ as follows:

Corollaries

As mentioned above, the theorem includes numerous earlier transcendence results concerning the exponential function, such as the Hermite–Lindemann theorem and Gelfond–Schneider theorem. It is not quite as encompassing as the still unproven Schanuel's conjecture, and does not imply the six exponentials theorem nor, clearly, the still open four exponentials conjecture.

The main reason Gelfond desired an extension of his result was not just for a slew of new transcendental numbers. In 1935 he used the tools he had developed to prove the Gelfond–Schneider theorem to derive a lower bound for the quantity

where β1 and β2 are algebraic and λ1 and λ2 are in .[2] Baker's proof gave lower bounds for quantities like the above but with arbitrarily many terms, and he could use these bounds to develop effective means of tackling Diophantine equations and to solve Gauss' class number problem.

Extensions

Baker's theorem grants us the linear independence over the algebraic numbers of logarithms of algebraic numbers. This is weaker than proving their algebraic independence. So far no progress has been made on this problem at all. It has been conjectured[3] that if λ1, …, λn are elements of that are linearly independent over the rational numbers, then they are algebraically independent too. This is a special case of Schanuel's conjecture, but so far it remains to be proved that there even exist two algebraic numbers whose logarithms are algebraically independent. Indeed, Baker's theorem rules out linear relations between logarithms of algebraic numbers unless there are trivial reasons for them; the next most simple case, that of ruling out homogeneous quadratic relations, is the still open four exponentials conjecture.

Similarly, extending the result to algebraic independence but in the p-adic setting, and using the p-adic logarithm function, remains an open problem. It is known that proving algebraic independence of linearly independent p-adic logarithms of algebraic p-adic numbers would prove Leopoldt's conjecture on the p-adic ranks of units of a number field.

See also

Notes

  1. See the final paragraph of Gel'fond (1960).
  2. See Gel'fond (1960) and Sprindžuk (1993) for details.
  3. Waldschmidt (2000), conjecture 1.15.

References

This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.