A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, Boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arguments, that is, for each combination of values taken by their logical variables.[1] In particular, truth tables can be used to show whether a propositional expression is true for all legitimate input values, that is, logically valid.
A truth table has one column for each input variable (for example, A and B), and one final column showing all of the possible results of the logical operation that the table represents (for example, A XOR B). Each row of the truth table contains one possible configuration of the input variables (for instance, A=true, B=false), and the result of the operation for those values.
A truth table is a structured representation that presents all possible combinations of truth values for the input variables of a Boolean function and their corresponding output values. A function f from A to F is a special relation, a subset of A×F, which simply means that f can be listed as a list of input-output pairs. Clearly, for the Boolean functions, the output belongs to a binary set, i.e. F = {0, 1}. For an n-ary Boolean function, the inputs come from a domain that is itself a Cartesian product of binary sets corresponding to the input Boolean variables. For example for a binary function, f(A, B), the domain of f is A×B, which can be listed as: A×B = {(A = 0, B = 0), (A = 0, B = 1), (A = 1, B = 0), (A = 1, B = 1)}. Each element in the domain represents a combination of input values for the variables A and B. These combinations now can be combined with the output of the function corresponding to that combination, thus forming the set of input-output pairs as a special relation that is subset of A×F. For a relation to be a function, the special requirement is that each element of the domain of the function must be mapped to one and only one member of the codomain. Thus, the function f itself can be listed as: f = {((0, 0), f0), ((0, 1), f1), ((1, 0), f2), ((1, 1), f3)}, where f0, f1, f2, and f3 are each Boolean, 0 or 1, values as members of the codomain {0, 1}, as the outputs corresponding to the member of the domain, respectively. Rather than a list (set) given above, the truth table then presents these input-output pairs in a tabular format, in which each row corresponds to a member of the domain paired with its corresponding output value, 0 or 1. Of course, for the Boolean functions, we do not have to list all the members of the domain with their images in the codomain; we can simply list the mappings that map the member to "1", because all the others will have to be mapped to "0" automatically (that leads us to the minterms idea).
Ludwig Wittgenstein is generally credited with inventing and popularizing the truth table in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, which was completed in 1918 and published in 1921.[2] Such a system was also independently proposed in 1921 by Emil Leon Post.[3]
Nullary operations
There are 2 nullary operations:
- Always true
- Never true, unary falsum
Logical true
The output value is always true, because this operator has zero operands and therefore no input values
p | T |
---|---|
T | T |
F | T |
Logical false
The output value is never true: that is, always false, because this operator has zero operands and therefore no input values
p | F |
---|---|
T | F |
F | F |
Unary operations
There are 2 unary operations:
- Unary identity
- Unary negation
Logical identity
Logical identity is an operation on one logical value p, for which the output value remains p.
The truth table for the logical identity operator is as follows:
p | p |
---|---|
T | T |
F | F |
Logical negation
Logical negation is an operation on one logical value, typically the value of a proposition, that produces a value of true if its operand is false and a value of false if its operand is true.
The truth table for NOT p (also written as ¬p, Np, Fpq, or ~p) is as follows:
p | ¬p |
---|---|
T | F |
F | T |
Binary operations
There are 16 possible truth functions of two binary variables, each operator has its own name.
Truth table
Here is an extended truth table giving definitions of all sixteen possible truth functions of two Boolean variables p and q:[note 1]
p q F0 NOR1 ↚2 ¬p3 NIMPLY4 ¬q5 XOR6 NAND7 AND8 XNOR9 q10 IMPLY11 p12 ←13 OR14 T15 T T F F F F F F F F T T T T T T T T T F F F F F T T T T F F F F T T T T F T F F T T F F T T F F T T F F T T F F F T F T F T F T F T F T F T F T Com ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ Assoc ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ ✓ Adj F0 NOR1 ↛4 ¬q5 NIMPLY2 ¬p3 XOR6 NAND7 AND8 XNOR9 p12 IMPLY13 q10 →11 OR14 T15 Neg T15 OR14 ←13 p12 IMPLY11 q10 XNOR9 AND8 NAND7 XOR6 ¬q5 NIMPLY4 ¬p3 ↚2 NOR1 F0 Dual T15 NAND7 →11 ¬p3 ←13 ¬q5 XNOR9 NOR1 OR14 XOR6 q10 ↚2 p12 ↛4 AND8 F0 L id F F T T T,F T F R id F F T T T,F T F
where
- T = true.
- F = false.
- The superscripts 0 to 15 is the number resulting from reading the four truth values as a binary number with F = 0 and T = 1.
- The Com row indicates whether an operator, op, is commutative - P op Q = Q op P.
- The Assoc row indicates whether an operator, op, is associative - (P op Q) op R = P op (Q op R).
- The Adj row shows the operator op2 such that P op Q = Q op2 P.
- The Neg row shows the operator op2 such that P op Q = ¬(P op2 Q).
- The Dual row shows the dual operation obtained by interchanging T with F, and AND with OR.
- The L id row shows the operator's left identities if it has any - values I such that I op Q = Q.
- The R id row shows the operator's right identities if it has any - values I such that P op I = P.[note 2]
Wittgenstein table
In proposition 5.101 of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus,[4] Wittgenstein listed the table above as follows:
Truthvalues Operator Operation name Tractatus[note 3] 0 (F F F F)(p, q) ⊥ false Opq Contradiction p and not p; and q and not q 1 (F F F T)(p, q) NOR p ↓ q Xpq Logical NOR neither p nor q 2 (F F T F)(p, q) ↚ p ↚ q Mpq Converse nonimplication q and not p 3 (F F T T)(p, q) ¬p, ~p ¬p Np, Fpq Negation not p 4 (F T F F)(p, q) ↛ p ↛ q Lpq Material nonimplication p and not q 5 (F T F T)(p, q) ¬q, ~q ¬q Nq, Gpq Negation not q 6 (F T T F)(p, q) XOR p ⊕ q Jpq Exclusive disjunction p or q, but not both 7 (F T T T)(p, q) NAND p ↑ q Dpq Logical NAND not both p and q 8 (T F F F)(p, q) AND p ∧ q Kpq Logical conjunction p and q 9 (T F F T)(p, q) XNOR p iff q Epq Logical biconditional if p then q; and if q then p 10 (T F T F)(p, q) q q Hpq Projection function q 11 (T F T T)(p, q) p → q if p then q Cpq Material implication if p then q 12 (T T F F)(p, q) p p Ipq Projection function p 13 (T T F T)(p, q) p ← q if q then p Bpq Converse implication if q then p 14 (T T T F)(p, q) OR p ∨ q Apq Logical disjunction p or q 15 (T T T T)(p, q) ⊤ true Vpq Tautology if p then p; and if q then q
The truth table represented by each row is obtained by appending the sequence given in Truthvaluesrow to the table[note 3]
p T T F F q T F T F
For example, the table
p T T F F q T F T F 11 T F T T
represents the truth table for Material implication.
Logical operators can also be visualized using Venn diagrams.
Logical conjunction (AND)
Logical conjunction is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true if both of its operands are true.
The truth table for p AND q (also written as p ∧ q, Kpq, p & q, or p q) is as follows:
p | q | p ∧ q |
---|---|---|
T | T | T |
T | F | F |
F | T | F |
F | F | F |
In ordinary language terms, if both p and q are true, then the conjunction p ∧ q is true. For all other assignments of logical values to p and to q the conjunction p ∧ q is false.
It can also be said that if p, then p ∧ q is q, otherwise p ∧ q is p.
Logical disjunction (OR)
Logical disjunction is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true if at least one of its operands is true.
The truth table for p OR q (also written as p ∨ q, Apq, p || q, or p + q) is as follows:
p | q | p ∨ q |
---|---|---|
T | T | T |
T | F | T |
F | T | T |
F | F | F |
Stated in English, if p, then p ∨ q is p, otherwise p ∨ q is q.
Logical implication
Logical implication and the material conditional are both associated with an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, which produces a value of false if the first operand is true and the second operand is false, and a value of true otherwise.
The truth table associated with the logical implication p implies q (symbolized as p ⇒ q, or more rarely Cpq) is as follows:
p | q | p ⇒ q |
---|---|---|
T | T | T |
T | F | F |
F | T | T |
F | F | T |
The truth table associated with the material conditional if p then q (symbolized as p → q) is as follows:
p | q | p → q |
---|---|---|
T | T | T |
T | F | F |
F | T | T |
F | F | T |
It may also be useful to note that p ⇒ q and p → q are equivalent to ¬p ∨ q.
Logical equality
Logical equality (also known as biconditional or exclusive nor) is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true if both operands are false or both operands are true.
The truth table for p XNOR q (also written as p ↔ q, Epq, p = q, or p ≡ q) is as follows:
p | q | p ↔ q |
---|---|---|
T | T | T |
T | F | F |
F | T | F |
F | F | T |
So p EQ q is true if p and q have the same truth value (both true or both false), and false if they have different truth values.
Exclusive disjunction
Exclusive disjunction is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true if one but not both of its operands is true.
The truth table for p XOR q (also written as Jpq, or p ⊕ q) is as follows:
p | q | p ⊕ q |
---|---|---|
T | T | F |
T | F | T |
F | T | T |
F | F | F |
For two propositions, XOR can also be written as (p ∧ ¬q) ∨ (¬p ∧ q).
Logical NAND
The logical NAND is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of false if both of its operands are true. In other words, it produces a value of true if at least one of its operands is false.
The truth table for p NAND q (also written as p ↑ q, Dpq, or p | q) is as follows:
p | q | p ↑ q |
---|---|---|
T | T | F |
T | F | T |
F | T | T |
F | F | T |
It is frequently useful to express a logical operation as a compound operation, that is, as an operation that is built up or composed from other operations. Many such compositions are possible, depending on the operations that are taken as basic or "primitive" and the operations that are taken as composite or "derivative".
In the case of logical NAND, it is clearly expressible as a compound of NOT and AND.
The negation of a conjunction: ¬(p ∧ q), and the disjunction of negations: (¬p) ∨ (¬q) can be tabulated as follows:
p | q | p ∧ q | ¬(p ∧ q) | ¬p | ¬q | (¬p) ∨ (¬q) |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
T | T | T | F | F | F | F |
T | F | F | T | F | T | T |
F | T | F | T | T | F | T |
F | F | F | T | T | T | T |
Logical NOR
The logical NOR is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true if both of its operands are false. In other words, it produces a value of false if at least one of its operands is true. ↓ is also known as the Peirce arrow after its inventor, Charles Sanders Peirce, and is a Sole sufficient operator.
The truth table for p NOR q (also written as p ↓ q, or Xpq) is as follows:
p | q | p ↓ q |
---|---|---|
T | T | F |
T | F | F |
F | T | F |
F | F | T |
The negation of a disjunction ¬(p ∨ q), and the conjunction of negations (¬p) ∧ (¬q) can be tabulated as follows:
p | q | p ∨ q | ¬(p ∨ q) | ¬p | ¬q | (¬p) ∧ (¬q) |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
T | T | T | F | F | F | F |
T | F | T | F | F | T | F |
F | T | T | F | T | F | F |
F | F | F | T | T | T | T |
Inspection of the tabular derivations for NAND and NOR, under each assignment of logical values to the functional arguments p and q, produces the identical patterns of functional values for ¬(p ∧ q) as for (¬p) ∨ (¬q), and for ¬(p ∨ q) as for (¬p) ∧ (¬q). Thus the first and second expressions in each pair are logically equivalent, and may be substituted for each other in all contexts that pertain solely to their logical values.
This equivalence is one of De Morgan's laws.
Size of truth tables
If there are n input variables then there are 2n possible combinations of their truth values. A given function may produce true or false for each combination so the number of different functions of n variables is the double exponential 22n.
n | 2n | 22n | |
---|---|---|---|
0 | 1 | 2 | |
1 | 2 | 4 | |
2 | 4 | 16 | |
3 | 8 | 256 | |
4 | 16 | 65,536 | |
5 | 32 | 4,294,967,296 | ≈ 4.3×109 |
6 | 64 | 18,446,744,073,709,551,616 | ≈ 1.8×1019 |
7 | 128 | 340,282,366,920,938,463,463,374,607,431,768,211,456 | ≈ 3.4×1038 |
8 | 256 | 115,792,089,237,316,195,423,570,985,008,687,907,853,269,984,665,640,564,039,457,584,007,913,129,639,936 | ≈ 1.2×1077 |
Truth tables for functions of three or more variables are rarely given.
Applications
Truth tables can be used to prove many other logical equivalences. For example, consider the following truth table:
T | T | F | T | T |
T | F | F | F | F |
F | T | T | T | T |
F | F | T | T | T |
This demonstrates the fact that is logically equivalent to .
Truth table for most commonly used logical operators
Here is a truth table that gives definitions of the 7 most commonly used out of the 16 possible truth functions of two Boolean variables P and Q:
P | Q | |||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
T | T | T | T | F | T | T | T | T |
T | F | F | T | T | F | F | T | F |
F | T | F | T | T | F | T | F | F |
F | F | F | F | F | T | T | T | T |
P | Q | |||||||
AND (conjunction) |
OR (disjunction) |
XOR (exclusive or) |
XNOR (exclusive nor) |
conditional "if-then" |
conditional "then-if" |
biconditional "if-and-only-if" | ||
where T means true and F means false |
Condensed truth tables for binary operators
For binary operators, a condensed form of truth table is also used, where the row headings and the column headings specify the operands and the table cells specify the result. For example, Boolean logic uses this condensed truth table notation:
|
|
This notation is useful especially if the operations are commutative, although one can additionally specify that the rows are the first operand and the columns are the second operand. This condensed notation is particularly useful in discussing multi-valued extensions of logic, as it significantly cuts down on combinatoric explosion of the number of rows otherwise needed. It also provides for quickly recognizable characteristic "shape" of the distribution of the values in the table which can assist the reader in grasping the rules more quickly.
Truth tables in digital logic
Truth tables are also used to specify the function of hardware look-up tables (LUTs) in digital logic circuitry. For an n-input LUT, the truth table will have 2^n values (or rows in the above tabular format), completely specifying a boolean function for the LUT. By representing each boolean value as a bit in a binary number, truth table values can be efficiently encoded as integer values in electronic design automation (EDA) software. For example, a 32-bit integer can encode the truth table for a LUT with up to 5 inputs.
When using an integer representation of a truth table, the output value of the LUT can be obtained by calculating a bit index k based on the input values of the LUT, in which case the LUT's output value is the kth bit of the integer. For example, to evaluate the output value of a LUT given an array of n boolean input values, the bit index of the truth table's output value can be computed as follows: if the ith input is true, let , else let . Then the kth bit of the binary representation of the truth table is the LUT's output value, where .
Truth tables are a simple and straightforward way to encode boolean functions, however given the exponential growth in size as the number of inputs increase, they are not suitable for functions with a large number of inputs. Other representations which are more memory efficient are text equations and binary decision diagrams.
Applications of truth tables in digital electronics
In digital electronics and computer science (fields of applied logic engineering and mathematics), truth tables can be used to reduce basic boolean operations to simple correlations of inputs to outputs, without the use of logic gates or code. For example, a binary addition can be represented with the truth table:
T | T | T | F |
T | F | F | T |
F | T | F | T |
F | F | F | F |
where A is the first operand, B is the second operand, C is the carry digit, and R is the result.
This truth table is read left to right:
- Value pair (A,B) equals value pair (C,R).
- Or for this example, A plus B equal result R, with the Carry C.
Note that this table does not describe the logic operations necessary to implement this operation, rather it simply specifies the function of inputs to output values.
With respect to the result, this example may be arithmetically viewed as modulo 2 binary addition, and as logically equivalent to the exclusive-or (exclusive disjunction) binary logic operation.
In this case it can be used for only very simple inputs and outputs, such as 1s and 0s. However, if the number of types of values one can have on the inputs increases, the size of the truth table will increase.
For instance, in an addition operation, one needs two operands, A and B. Each can have one of two values, zero or one. The number of combinations of these two values is 2×2, or four. So the result is four possible outputs of C and R. If one were to use base 3, the size would increase to 3×3, or nine possible outputs.
The first "addition" example above is called a half-adder. A full-adder is when the carry from the previous operation is provided as input to the next adder. Thus, a truth table of eight rows would be needed to describe a full adder's logic:
A B C* | C R 0 0 0 | 0 0 0 1 0 | 0 1 1 0 0 | 0 1 1 1 0 | 1 0 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 1 1 | 1 0 1 0 1 | 1 0 1 1 1 | 1 1 Same as previous, but.. C* = Carry from previous adder
History
Irving Anellis's research shows that C.S. Peirce appears to be the earliest logician (in 1883) to devise a truth table matrix.[5]
From the summary of Peirce's paper:
In 1997, John Shosky discovered, on the verso of a page of the typed transcript of Bertrand Russell's 1912 lecture on "The Philosophy of Logical Atomism" truth table matrices. The matrix for negation is Russell's, alongside of which is the matrix for material implication in the hand of Ludwig Wittgenstein. It is shown that an unpublished manuscript identified as composed by Peirce in 1893 includes a truth table matrix that is equivalent to the matrix for material implication discovered by John Shosky. An unpublished manuscript by Peirce identified as having been composed in 1883–84 in connection with the composition of Peirce's "On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation" that appeared in the American Journal of Mathematics in 1885 includes an example of an indirect truth table for the conditional.
See also
- Boolean domain
- Boolean-valued function
- Espresso heuristic logic minimizer
- Excitation table
- State-transition table
- First-order logic
- Functional completeness
- Karnaugh maps
- Logic gate
- Logical connective
- Logical graph
- Mathematical table
- Method of analytic tableaux
- Propositional calculus
- Truth function
- Decision table
Notes
- ↑ Information about notation may be found in (Bocheński 1959), (Enderton 2001), and (Quine 1982).
- ↑ The operators here with equal left and right identities (XOR, AND, XNOR, and OR) are also commutative monoids because they are also associative. While this distinction may be irrelevant in a simple discussion of logic, it can be quite important in more advanced mathematics. For example, in category theory an enriched category is described as a base category enriched over a monoid, and any of these operators can be used for enrichment.
- 1 2 Wittgenstein used a different mapping. In proposition 5.101 of the Tractatus one has to append Truthvaluesrow to the table
p T F T F q T T F F
References
- ↑ Enderton 2001
- ↑ von Wright, Georg Henrik (1955). "Ludwig Wittgenstein, A Biographical Sketch". The Philosophical Review. 64 (4): 527–545 (p. 532, note 9). doi:10.2307/2182631. JSTOR 2182631.
- ↑ Post, Emil (July 1921). "Introduction to a general theory of elementary propositions". American Journal of Mathematics. 43 (3): 163–185. doi:10.2307/2370324. hdl:2027/uiuo.ark:/13960/t9j450f7q. JSTOR 2370324.
- ↑ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (PDF). Proposition 5.101.
- ↑ Anellis, Irving H. (2012). "Peirce's Truth-functional Analysis and the Origin of the Truth Table". History and Philosophy of Logic. 33: 87–97. doi:10.1080/01445340.2011.621702. S2CID 170654885.
Works cited
- Bocheński, Józef Maria (1959). A Précis of Mathematical Logic. Translated by Bird, Otto. D. Reidel. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0592-9. ISBN 978-94-017-0592-9.
- Enderton, H. (2001). A Mathematical Introduction to Logic (2nd ed.). Harcourt Academic Press. ISBN 0-12-238452-0.
- Quine, W.V. (1982). Methods of Logic (4th ed.). Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-57175-4.
External links
- "Truth table", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]
- Truth Tables, Tautologies, and Logical Equivalence
- Anellis, Irving H. (2011). "Peirce's Truth-functional Analysis and the Origin of Truth Tables". arXiv:1108.2429 [math.HO].
- Converting truth tables into Boolean expressions