"A Defense of Abortion" is a moral philosophy essay by Judith Jarvis Thomson first published in Philosophy & Public Affairs in 1971. Granting for the sake of argument that the fetus has a right to life, Thomson uses thought experiments to argue that the right to life does not include, entail, or imply the right to use someone else's body to survive and that induced abortion is therefore morally permissible. Thomson's argument has many critics on both sides of the abortion debate,[1] yet it continues to receive defense.[2] Thomson's imaginative examples and controversial conclusions have made "A Defense of Abortion" perhaps "the most widely reprinted essay in all of contemporary philosophy".[3]
Overview
The violinist
In "A Defense of Abortion", Thomson grants for the sake of argument that the fetus has a right to life, but defends the permissibility of abortion by appealing to a thought experiment:
You wake up in the morning and find yourself back to back in bed with an unconscious violinist. A famous unconscious violinist. He has been found to have a fatal kidney ailment, and the Society of Music Lovers has canvassed all the available medical records and found that you alone have the right blood type to help. They have therefore kidnapped you, and last night the violinist's circulatory system was plugged into yours, so that your kidneys can be used to extract poisons from his blood as well as your own. [If he is unplugged from you now, he will die; but] in nine months he will have recovered from his ailment, and can safely be unplugged from you.[4]
Thomson argues that one can now permissibly unplug oneself from the violinist even though this will cause his death: this is due to limits on the right to life, which does not include the right to use another person's body, and so by unplugging the violinist, one does not violate his right to life but merely deprives him of something – the use of someone else's body – to which he has no right. "[I]f you do allow him to go on using your kidneys, this is a kindness on your part, and not something he can claim from you as his due."[5]
For the same reason, Thomson says, abortion does not violate the fetus's legitimate right to life, but merely deprives the fetus of something – the non-consensual use of the pregnant woman's body and life-supporting functions – to which it has no right. Thus, by choosing to terminate her pregnancy, Thomson concludes that a pregnant woman does not normally violate the fetus's right to life, but merely withdraws its use of her own body, which usually causes the fetus to die.[6]
Third-party participation – the "expanding child"
Thomson criticizes the common method of deducing a woman's right to abort from the permissibility of a third party committing the abortion. In most instances, a woman's right to abortion may hinge on the doctor's willingness to perform it. If the doctor refuses, then the pregnant woman is denied her right. To base the pregnant woman's right on the accordance or refusal of a doctor, she argues, is to ignore the pregnant woman's full personhood, and subsequently, her right to her own body. Thomson presents the hypothetical example of the 'expanding child':
Suppose you find yourself trapped in a tiny house with a growing child. I mean a very tiny house and a rapidly growing child – you are already up against the wall of the house and in a few minutes you'll be crushed to death. The child on the other hand won't be crushed to death; if nothing is done to stop him from growing he'll be hurt, but in the end, he'll simply burst open the house and walk out a free man.[7]
Thomson concedes that a third party indeed cannot make the choice to kill either the person being crushed or the child. However, this does not mean that the person being crushed cannot act in self-defense and attack the child to save his or her own life. To liken this to pregnancy, the mother can be thought to be the person inside the house, the fetus the growing child. In such a case, the mothers's life is being threatened, and the fetus is the one who threatens it. Because for no reason should the pregnant woman's life be threatened, and also for no reason is the fetus threatening it, both are innocent, and thus no third party can intervene. But, Thomson asserts, the person threatened can intervene, by which justification a mother can rightfully abort.[8]
Continuing, Thomson returns to the 'expanding child' example and points out:
For what we have to keep in mind is that the mother and the unborn child are not like two tenants in a small house, which has, by unfortunate mistake, been rented to both: the mother owns the house. The fact that she does adds to the offensiveness of deducing that the mother can do nothing from the supposition that third parties can do nothing. But it does more than this: it casts a bright light on the supposition that third parties can do nothing.[9]
If we say that no one may help the mother obtain an abortion, we fail to acknowledge her right over her own body (or property). Thomson says that we are not personally obligated to help the pregnant woman, though this does not rule out the possibility that someone else may act. As Thomson reminds, the house belongs to the pregnant woman; similarly, the body which holds a fetus also belongs to her.[10]
Pregnancy resulting from voluntary intercourse – "people-seeds"
To illustrate an example of pregnancy due to voluntary intercourse, Thomson presents the 'people-seeds' situation:
Again, suppose it were like this: people-seeds drift about in the air like pollen, and if you open your windows, one may drift in and take root in your carpets or upholstery. You don't want children, so you fix up your windows with fine mesh screens, the very best you can buy. As can happen, however, and on very, very rare occasions does happen, one of the screens is defective; and a seed drifts in and takes root.[11]
In this example, the people-seeds flying through the window represent conception, despite the precautionary mesh screen, which functions as contraception. The woman in question does not want a people-seed to root itself in her house, and so she takes the necessary precautions and measures to protect herself with the best mesh screens, and then voluntarily opens the windows. However, in the event that a single people-seed finds its way through the window screens, unwelcome as it may be, does the simple fact that the woman knowingly risked such an occurrence when opening her window deny her the ability to rid her house of the intruder? Thomson notes that some may argue the affirmative to this question, claiming that "... after all you could have lived out your life with bare floors and furniture, or with sealed windows and doors".[11] But by this logic, she says, any woman could avoid pregnancy due to rape by simply having a hysterectomy – an extreme procedure simply to safeguard against such a possibility. Thomson concludes that although there may be times when the fetus does have a right to the pregnant woman's body, certainly in most cases the fetus does not have a right to her body. This analogy raises the issue of whether all abortions are unjust killing.[11]
Caveats
Thomson does not support abortion in all circumstances, she gives as an example a hypothetical woman who seeks a late termination of pregnancy; "just to avoid the nuisance of postponing a trip abroad" and declares this to be "positively indecent".
Thomson also explicitly rejects the claim that pregnant women have a right to kill their offspring. She argues for the right of the pregnant woman to stop being pregnant, even if this results in the death of the offspring, but not for the right to ensure that the offspring is dead. If, for example, a late-term abortion accidentally results in the birth of a living baby, then Thomson would conclude that the mother has no right to kill the baby.
Criticism
Critics of Thomson's argument generally grant the permissibility of unplugging the violinist, but seek to block the inference that abortion is permissible by arguing that there are morally relevant differences between the violinist scenario and typical cases of abortion. One notable exception to this general agreement is Peter Singer, who argues that, despite our intuitions, a utilitarian calculus implies that one is morally obliged to stay connected to the violinist.[12]
The most common objection is that Thomson's violinist argument can justify abortion only in cases of rape, though Thomson uses separate analogies to argue in cases other than rape. In the violinist scenario, the pregnant woman was kidnapped: she did not consent to having the violinist plugged into her and she did nothing to cause the violinist to be plugged in, just as a woman who is pregnant due to rape did nothing to cause the pregnancy. But in some cases of abortion, the pregnant woman had voluntary intercourse, and thus has either tacitly consented to allow the fetus to use her body (the tacit consent objection),[13] or else has a duty to sustain the fetus because the pregnant woman herself caused the fetus to stand in need of her body (the responsibility objection).[14] Other common objections turn on the claim that the fetus is the pregnant woman's child, whereas the violinist is a stranger (the stranger versus offspring objection),[15] or that abortion directly and intentionally kills the fetus, whereas unplugging the violinist merely lets him die of natural causes (the killing versus letting die objection).[15]
Defenders of Thomson's argument reply that the alleged disanalogies between the violinist scenario and typical cases of abortion do not matter, either because the factors that critics appeal to are not genuinely morally relevant, or because those factors are morally relevant but do not apply to abortion in the way that critics have claimed. Thomson's defenders also point to her 'people-seeds' argument as a strong analogy to typical cases of abortion.[16]
Thomson's article, by positing a moral justification for abortion even if one grants a fetal right to life, opened up a new avenue in the philosophical debate about the ethics of abortion. Critics of her view have formulated many objections to her argument, and defenders have responded in kind in a back and forth that continues in philosophy journals.
See also
- Philosophical aspects of the abortion debate – for more detail about how this debate has progressed beyond Thomson's article
Notes
- ↑ E.g. Schwarz 1990 (chap. 8), Beckwith 1993 (chap. 7), and Lee 1996 (chap. 4) on the anti-abortion side; Tooley 1972 (pp. 52–53), Warren 1973, Steinbock 1992 (p. 78), and McMahan 2002 on the pro-choice side.
- ↑ Kamm 1992; Boonin 2003, chap. 4.
- ↑ Parent 1986, p. vii.
- ↑ Thomson 1971, pp. 48–49.
- ↑ Thomson 1971, p. 55.
- ↑ Thomson 1971, p. 63; Boonin 2003, pp. 133–134.
- ↑ Thomson 1971, p. 52.
- ↑ Thomson 1971, pp. 52–53.
- ↑ Thomson 1971, p. 53.
- ↑ Thomson 1971, p. 54.
- 1 2 3 Thomson 1971, p. 59.
- ↑ Singer 2011, p. 134.
- ↑ E.g. Warren 1973; Steinbock 1992, p. 78.
- ↑ E.g. Beckwith 1993, chap. 7; McMahan 2002.
- 1 2 E.g. Schwarz 1990, chap. 8; Beckwith 1993, chap. 7; McMahan 2002.
- ↑ Boonin 2003, chap. 4.
Bibliography
- Beckwith, Francis J. (1993). Politically Correct Death: Answering the Arguments for Abortion Rights. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Baker Books.
- Boonin, David (2003). A Defense of Abortion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Kamm, F. M. (1992). Creation and Abortion: A Study in Moral and Legal Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Lee, Patrick (1996). Abortion and Unborn Human Life. Washington: Catholic University of America Press.
- McMahan, Jeff (2002). The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Parent, William (1986). "Editor's Preface". Rights, Restitution, and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory. By Thomson, Judith Jarvis. Parent, William (ed.). Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. pp. vii–x. ISBN 978-0-674-76980-9.
- Schwarz, Stephen D. (1990). The Moral Question of Abortion. Chicago: Loyola University Press.
- Singer, Peter (2011). Practical Ethics (3rd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.
- Steinbock, Bonnie (1992). Life Before Birth: The Moral and Legal Status of Embryos and Fetuses. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Thomson, Judith Jarvis (1971). "A Defense of Abortion". Philosophy and Public Affairs. 1 (1): 47–66. ISSN 1088-4963. JSTOR 2265091.
- Tooley, Michael (1972). "Abortion and Infanticide". Philosophy & Public Affairs. 2 (1): 37–65. ISSN 1088-4963. JSTOR 2264919.
- Warren, Mary Anne (1973). "On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion". The Monist. 57 (1): 43–61. doi:10.5840/monist197357133. ISSN 2153-3601. JSTOR 27902294. PMID 11661013.
Further reading
- Bourbaki, Nicola (2001). "Living High and Letting Die". Philosophy. 76 (3): 435–442. doi:10.1017/S0031819101000377. ISSN 1469-817X. JSTOR 3751780. S2CID 145357729.
- Finnis, John (1973). "The Rights and Wrongs of Abortion: A Reply to Judith Thomson". Philosophy and Public Affairs. 2 (2): 117–145. ISSN 1088-4963. JSTOR 2265137. PMID 11663360.
- Hershenov, David B. (2001). "Abortions and Distortions: An Analysis of Morally Irrelevant Factors in Thomson's Violinist Thought Experiment". Social Theory and Practice. 27 (1): 129–148. doi:10.5840/soctheorpract200127124. ISSN 2154-123X. JSTOR 23559045. PMID 12564447.
- Lee, Patrick; George, Robert P. (2005). "The Wrong of Abortion". In Cohen, Andrew I.; Wellman, Christopher Heath (eds.). Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics. Malden, Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing. pp. 13–26, esp. pp. 20–21. ISBN 978-1-4051-1548-3.
- Parks, Brian D. (2006). "The Natural–Artificial Distinction and Conjoined Twins: A Response to Judith Thomson's Argument for Abortion Rights". The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly. 6 (4): 671–680. doi:10.5840/ncbq2006646. ISSN 1938-1646.
- Thomson, Judith Jarvis (1973). "Rights and Deaths". Philosophy and Public Affairs. 2 (2): 146–159. ISSN 1088-4963. JSTOR 2265138. PMID 11663361.
- Wiland, Eric (2000). "Unconscious Violinists and the Use of Analogies in Moral Argument". Journal of Medical Ethics. 26 (6): 466–468. doi:10.1136/jme.26.6.466. ISSN 1473-4257. PMC 1733303. PMID 11129849.
External links
- A Defense of Abortion, full text