In topology and related areas of mathematics, a subnet is a generalization of the concept of subsequence to the case of nets. The analogue of "subsequence" for nets is the notion of a "subnet". The definition is not completely straightforward, but is designed to allow as many theorems about subsequences to generalize to nets as possible.

There are three non-equivalent definitions of "subnet". The first definition of a subnet was introduced by John L. Kelley in 1955[1] and later, Stephen Willard introduced his own (non-equivalent) variant of Kelley's definition in 1970.[1] Subnets in the sense of Willard and subnets in the sense of Kelley are the most commonly used definitions of "subnet"[1] but they are each not equivalent to the concept of "subordinate filter", which is the analog of "subsequence" for filters (they are not equivalent in the sense that there exist subordinate filters on whose filter/subordinate–filter relationship cannot be described in terms of the corresponding net/subnet relationship). A third definition of "subnet" (not equivalent to those given by Kelley or Willard) that is equivalent to the concept of "subordinate filter" was introduced independently by Smiley (1957), Aarnes and Andenaes (1972), Murdeshwar (1983), and possibly others, although it is not often used.[1]

This article discusses the definition due to Willard (the other definitions are described in the article Filters in topology#Non–equivalence of subnets and subordinate filters).

Definitions

There are several different non-equivalent definitions of "subnet" and this article will use the definition introduced in 1970 by Stephen Willard,[1] which is as follows: If and are nets in a set from directed sets and respectively, then is said to be a subnet of (in the sense of Willard or a Willard–subnet[1]) if there exists a monotone final function

such that

A function is monotone, order-preserving, and an order homomorphism if whenever then and it is called final if its image is cofinal in The set being cofinal in means that for every there exists some such that that is, for every there exists an such that [note 1]

Since the net is the function and the net is the function the defining condition may be written more succinctly and cleanly as either or where denotes function composition and is just notation for the function

Subnets versus subsequences

Importantly, a subnet is not merely the restriction of a net to a directed subset of its domain In contrast, by definition, a subsequence of a given sequence is a sequence formed from the given sequence by deleting some of the elements without disturbing the relative positions of the remaining elements. Explicitly, a sequence is said to be a subsequence of if there exists a strictly increasing sequence of positive integers such that for every (that is to say, such that ). The sequence can be canonically identified with the function defined by Thus a sequence is a subsequence of if and only if there exists a strictly increasing function such that

Subsequences are subnets

Every subsequence is a subnet because if is a subsequence of then the map defined by is an order-preserving map whose image is cofinal in its codomain and satisfies for all

Sequence and subnet but not a subsequence

The sequence is not a subsequence of although it is a subnet because the map defined by is an order-preserving map whose image is and satisfies for all [note 2]

While a sequence is a net, a sequence has subnets that are not subsequences. The key difference is that subnets can use the same point in the net multiple times and the indexing set of the subnet can have much larger cardinality. Using the more general definition where we do not require monotonicity, a sequence is a subnet of a given sequence, if and only if it can be obtained from some subsequence by repeating its terms and reordering them.[2]

Subnet of a sequence that is not a sequence

A subnet of a sequence is not necessarily a sequence.[3] For an example, let be directed by the usual order and define by letting be the ceiling of Then is an order-preserving map (because it is a non-decreasing function) whose image is a cofinal subset of its codomain. Let be any sequence (such as a constant sequence, for instance) and let for every (in other words, let ). This net is not a sequence since its domain is an uncountable set. However, is a subnet of the sequence since (by definition) holds for every Thus is a subnet of that is not a sequence.

Furthermore, the sequence is also a subnet of since the inclusion map (that sends ) is an order-preserving map whose image is a cofinal subset of its codomain and holds for all Thus and are (simultaneously) subnets of each another.

Subnets induced by subsets

Suppose is an infinite set and is a sequence. Then is a net on that is also a subnet of (take to be the inclusion map ). This subnet in turn induces a subsequence by defining as the smallest value in (that is, let and let for every integer ). In this way, every infinite subset of induces a canonical subnet that may be written as a subsequence. However, as demonstrated below, not every subnet of a sequence is a subsequence.

Applications

The definition generalizes some key theorems about subsequences:

  • A net converges to if and only if every subnet of converges to
  • A net has a cluster point if and only if it has a subnet that converges to
  • A topological space is compact if and only if every net in has a convergent subnet (see net for a proof).

Taking be the identity map in the definition of "subnet" and requiring to be a cofinal subset of leads to the concept of a cofinal subnet, which turns out to be inadequate since, for example, the second theorem above fails for the Tychonoff plank if we restrict ourselves to cofinal subnets.

Clustering and closure

If is a net in a subset and if is a cluster point of then In other words, every cluster point of a net in a subset belongs to the closure of that set.

If is a net in then the set of all cluster points of in is equal to[3]

where for each

Convergence versus clustering

If a net converges to a point then is necessarily a cluster point of that net.[3] The converse is not guaranteed in general. That is, it is possible for to be a cluster point of a net but for to not converge to However, if clusters at then there exists a subnet of that converges to This subnet can be explicitly constructed from and the neighborhood filter at as follows: make

into a directed set by declaring that

then and is a subnet of since the map

is a monotone function whose image is a cofinal subset of and

Thus, a point is a cluster point of a given net if and only if it has a subnet that converges to [3]

See also

Notes

  1. Some authors use a more general definition of a subnet. In this definition, the map is required to satisfy the condition: For every there exists a such that whenever Such a map is final but not necessarily monotone.
  2. Indeed, this is because and for every in other words, when considered as functions on the sequence is just the identity map on while

Citations

  1. 1 2 3 4 5 6 Schechter 1996, pp. 157–168.
  2. Gähler, Werner (1977). Grundstrukturen der Analysis I. Akademie-Verlag, Berlin., Satz 2.8.3, p. 81
  3. 1 2 3 4 Willard 2004, pp. 73–77.

References

This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.